The Nature & Goals of Communism / Socialism

The Nature & Goals of Communism / Socialism

Overview

This section of Discover The Networks examines the worldview and objectives of communism and socialism. David Horowitz’s 1998 essay, “Marx’s Manifesto: 150 Years of Evil,” offers an excellent overview of this topic


When the Soviet Union fell, the statues of Lenin were toppled throughout the Soviet empire and the head of Karl Marx was severed once and for all from any connection to a body politic. Yet the lips of the severed head continue to move.

In the West, leading intellectuals, many who would not allow themselves to be called Marxists, profess to hear a message they insist is relevant to our times. Thus, the rush [in 1998] to celebrate the 150th anniversary of the publication of the Communist Manifesto, the only text that most of the millions of soldiers in Marxist vanguards around the world ever read.

The Manifesto was an incitement to totalitarian ambitions whose results were far bloodier than those inspired by Mein Kampf. In it Marx announced the doom of free market societies, declared the liberal bourgeoisie to be a “ruling class” and the democratic state its puppet, summoned proletarians and their intellectual vanguard to begin civil wars in their own countries, and thereby launched the most destructive movement in human history….

[The Manifesto’s] principal thesis claiming to analyze complex societies on the basis of a single structure — economic class — is announced in its very first line: “The history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggle.”

The Manifesto’s message is: Civil War. This hypothesis is really the essence and sum of the Manifesto which is not a call to thought, but — and this should never be forgotten — a call to arms. The striking (and reprehensible) thesis of the Manifesto is that democratic societies are not really different in kind from the aristocratic and slave societies that required revolutions to overthrow. Despite surface appearances, despite the fact that in contrast to all previous societies, democracy makes the people “sovereign,” democratic capitalism is “unmasked” by Marx as an “oppressive” and tyrannical society like all the rest, and therefore requires extra-legal and violent means to liberate its victims from its yoke. That is why those who have been inspired by the Manifesto have declared war on the liberal societies of the West and have spilled so much blood and spread so much misery in our time.

The meaning of the first sentence of the Manifesto, then, is this: All (non-socialist) societies are divided into classes that are “oppressed” and those who oppress them. Capitalism is no different, even though its revolutions may have instituted democratic political structures designed to enfranchise the “oppressed.” For the very idea of democracy in a society where private property exists, according to the Manifesto, is an illusion: “The executive of the modern state is but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie.” In other words, democratic elections are a sham. Civil war is the political answer to humanity’s problems: “Workers of the world unite, you have nothing to lose but your chains.” The solution to all fundamental social problems — to war, to poverty, to economic inequality — lies in a conflict that will rip society apart and create a new revolutionary world from its ruins. This is the enduring and poisonous message of the Manifesto, and why its believers have left such a trail of human slaughter in their path as they set about to create a progressive future.

Almost every important analytic thesis of the Manifesto — including its opening statement — is patently false. History is not the history of class struggle, as defined by Marx, i.e., the struggle of economic oppressor and oppressed. Not even the historical event which provided the basis for Marx’s theoretical model, the French Revolution, is explicable in these terms. Historians like Simon Schama and Francis Furet have established, beyond any reasonable doubt, that capitalism was already thriving under the monarchy, and it was the nobility, not the bourgeoisie, that upended the ancien régime). When we look at the twentieth century, whose course has largely been determined by forces of nationalism and racism, which Marx utterly discounted, the hopeless inadequacy of his theories becomes impossible, except for those blinded by faith, to ignore.

According to Marx, the bourgeois epoch possesses a distinctive feature: “It has simplified the class antagonisms: Society as a whole is more and more splitting up into two great hostile camps, into two great classes, directly facing each other: Bourgeoisie and Proletariat.” But, of course, it hasn’t. Which is one reason why Marxism has failed, as a program, in all the industrialized countries.

In fact, much of the Marxist critique of capitalism reflects nothing so much as a romantic longing for a feudal past in which social status was pre-ordained and irrevocable, and stamped every individual with a destiny and a grace: “The bourgeoisie has stripped of its halo every occupation hitherto honoured and looked up to with reverent awe. It has converted the physician, the lawyer, the priest, the poet, the man of science, into its paid wage labourers.”

Of course, it has not exactly done this either. More likely it has turned physician, lawyer, scientist, and poet into entrepreneurs themselves. In the open societies created by capitalist revolutionaries, they can set up as independent contractors; they can incorporate themselves; and they can move up the social and economic scale to heights undreamed of when their status may have been “reverential” but where it was also fixed by the immutable relations of an authentic “class society,” which bourgeois society is not. The complexity and fluidity of class structure in developed capitalist societies has made a mockery of the core principles of Marxist belief.

The Manifesto’s False Vision of the Social Future

Marx was a first-rate intellect and a brilliant writer, and his descriptions of the progressive economic expansion of market societies under the leadership of the “bourgeoisie” are memorable and provide most of the basis for claims that the Manifesto is an accurate and “prescient” work. Marx famously extolled the capitalist class for constantly “revolutionizing the forces of production,” concluding: “The bourgeoisie, during its rule of scarce one hundred years, has created more massive and more colossal productive forces than have all preceding generations together.”

This sentence encapsulates both the seductive power of Marx’s writing and the sinister import of his theory. The description would seem to be an endorsement of capitalism, indicating the immense value to all members of society in the encouragement it has provided to an entrepreneurial class to create more social wealth than the world has ever known. It would hardly seem to provide an argument for the permanent war that Marx goes on to advocate against the bourgeoisie in the name of human progress. But even in the sentence quoted, one sees how the theory is designed to cancel the praise. Marx identifies the creative entrepreneurs as “rulers” in a sense designed to parallel that of absolutist monarchs and slave-owners, and thus to detach them from the reality of their achievement and from the fact that they earn the power they accumulate, and thus to incite social resentment and hatred against them. The theory further postulates that the productive forces these entrepreneurs have created have “outgrown” them, and make it necessary to destroy their “rule.”

In Marx’s colorful prose: “Modern bourgeois society … is like the sorcerer, who is no longer able to control the powers of the nether world whom he has called up by his spells.” Marx is referring here to the business cycle and its economic crises.

In these crises there breaks out an epidemic that, in all earlier epochs, would have seemed an absurdity — the epidemic of over-production. Society suddenly finds itself put back into a state of momentary barbarism; it appears as if a famine, a universal war of devastation had cut off the supply of every means of subsistence.

According to Marx the bourgeoisie is at war with the very forces of production that it has called into being (“The weapons with which the bourgeoisie felled feudalism to the ground are now turned against the bourgeoisie itself.”) And there is more. The forces of production called into being by the bourgeoisie have also created a class, the proletariat, which is its victim and its antagonist. The proletariat has no property itself, and therefore is in a position to abolish private property which is the “condition” of bourgeois production and bourgeois oppression, to remove the bourgeois “rulers” from their corporate thrones and to create a cooperative society in which the economy can be organized according to a “social plan.” This development emanating from the logic of History that Marx has discovered, has all the inevitability of a natural force:

“The advance of industry, whose involuntary promoter is the bourgeoisie, replaces the isolation of the labourers, due to competition, by their revolutionary combination, due to association. The development of Modern Industry, therefore, cuts from under its feet the very foundation on which the bourgeoisie produces and appropriates products. What the bourgeoisie, therefore, produces, above all, is its own grave-diggers. Its fall and the victory of the proletariat are equally inevitable.”

Well, not really.

The Manifesto’s Poisonous Legacy

Under the spell of prose like this, whole generations of “progressives” have been blinded to the obvious bounties of democratic capitalist societies and encouraged to make war on them, and with a nihilistic fury inspired by illusions of “social justice” producing human tragedy beyond measure. The heirs of Marx are still at it. In the wake of the Communist catastrophe, they are willing to acknowledge only that Marx’s economic categories are too narrow and that the proletariat has failed to make the revolution. But the core Marxist model, the model which proposes that democratic societies are oppressive and tyrannical, that they deserve not fundamental allegiance and constructive attention but venomous scorn and nihilistic rejection, that democratic processes and institutions are a sham, that the just solution to social problems lies along the path of civil confrontation and political warfare — this model is alive and well among radical feminists, racial separatists, queer nationalists, and the rag-tag intellectual army of post-modernists, critical theorists, and kitsch Marxists that inhabit our universities and evidently our editorial rooms as well….

[W]hat needs to be emphasized … is that Marx was totally, tragically, destructively wrong. He was wrong about the oppressive nature of the bourgeoisie and the outmoded nature of capitalist production, wrong about the increasing misery of the working class, and wrong about its liberating powers, wrong about the increasing concentration of wealth and the increasing polarization of class under capitalism, wrong about the labor theory of value and the falling rate of profit, and wrong about the possibility of creating an advanced and democratic industrial society by abolishing private property and the market in order to adopt a “social plan.”

If Marx’s economics were already outdated and false when he wrote the Manifesto, even worse was his political ignorance. He was, in particular, disastrously deaf to all the resonances of the Anglo-American constitutional tradition and the accumulated democratic wisdom ascending from the Magna Carta to the American Constitution. Here in its implacable arrogance is how the “visionary” prophet who wrote the Manifesto actually saw the political future:

“When, in the course of development, class distinctions have disappeared, and all production has been concentrated in the hands of a vast association of the whole nation, the public power will lose its political character. Political power, properly so called, is merely the organized power of one class for oppressing another. If the proletariat during its contest with the bourgeoisie is compelled, by the force of circumstances, to organize itself as a class, if, by means of a revolution, it makes itself the ruling class, and, as such, sweeps away by force the old conditions of production, then it will, along with these conditions, have swept away the conditions for the existence of class antagonisms and of classes generally, and will thereby have abolished its own supremacy as a class.”

One billion people have been impounded in totalitarian states and gulags, and one hundred million people have been murdered in our lifetime by Marxists acting on these false premises. That they should be endorsed today by anyone at all is a moral disgrace. This is what we should remember on the 150th anniversary of Marx’s destructive work. Political power is not “merely the organized power of one class for oppressing another.” In democratic market societies, where social mobility is fluid, the people are sovereign and the rule of law prevails, classes do not “oppress” one another, and those who inflame the passions of revolution are inciting their followers to criminal acts. Period.

Conclusion

Private property may be the basis of class divisions, as Marxists claim, but private property has been proven by all history to be the indispensable bulwark of human liberty, the only basis for producing general economic prosperity and social wealth that human beings have yet discovered. There are no democratic societies, or industrial societies or post-industrial societies that are not based on private property and economic markets. Those who make war on private property, make war on human liberty and human well-being.

Additional Resources:


The Socialist Phenomenon (Click on title to view the entire book)
By Igor Shafarevich
1975

Marx’s Manifesto: 150 Years of Evil
By David Horowitz
May 27, 1998

The Religious Roots of Radicalism
By David Horowitz
1998

Why Socialism Failed
By Mark Perry
June 1995

Just What Was Fundamentally Wrong with Bolshevism?
By Steven Plaut
November 29, 2012

If Obama Were a Marxist, What Would He Believe?
By Kelly O’Connell
October 17, 2009

Why the Left Is Reactionary
By Barry Loberfeld
June 12, 2006

Socialism, Free Enterprise, and the Common Good
By Robert A. Sirico
May 2007

Why Socialism Will Always Be with Us
By David Solway
September 13, 2016

Why Socialism Is on the Rise
By Ben Shapiro
January 8, 2014

Socialist or Fascist
By Thomas Sowell
June 12, 2012

PERSONAL REFLECTIONS OF A FORMER COMMUNIST:

The Road to Nowhere
By David Horowitz
October 1990

Unnecessary Losses
By David Horowitz
April 1987

VIDEOS:

Ten Things You Should Know about Socialism
By Thomas J. DiLorenzo (Mises Institute)
July 20, 2018

Heaven on Earth: The Rise and Fall of Socialism
June 2014

Understanding Marxism: The Enemy of Being is Having
By C. Bradley Thompson (Prager U)

Understanding Marxism: From Each According to His Ability…
By C. Bradley Thompson (Prager U)

Understanding Marxism: Change the World
By C. Bradley Thompson (Prager U)

Yugoslavian Issues Warning To All Americans
July 2020

The Socialist Temptation
By Dinesh D’Souza
October 2019

Capitalism or Socialism: Which One Is More Democratic?
By Dinesh D’Souza (Prager University)

Loch Ness Socialism
By Bill Whittle
September 25, 2014

BOOKS:

The Problem with Socialism
By Thomas DiLorenzo
2016

Heaven on Earth: The Rise and Fall of Socialism
By Joshua Muravchik
2002

 | 
© Copyright 2024, DiscoverTheNetworks.org